Rethinking Disability

  • Home
  • Projects
  • News
  • Agenda
  • Blog
  • Publications
  • About
  • Members
  • Search

Theoretical Approaches to the Human Rights of Marginalized and Excluded Individuals or Groups – Part I: A Short Critique of Human Dignity

18 September 2017 by Veronika Flegar in Blog Rethinking Disability

In an earlier post on this blog Paul van Trigt pointed to the frequent neglect of viewing human rights in their larger historical context. This is not only true for historians but, arguably, even more so for human rights lawyers. Due to this neglect, human rights lawyers seem to sometimes suffer a bias towards the salience of human rights and seem to be primarily preoccupied with the interpretation of international treaties and case law. Such interpretations often neglect to question the human rights system or its underlying assumptions as such. Yet, a more critical approach towards the central ideas of international human rights law seems necessary in order to build a sustainable system that is to the benefit of all human beings – including persons or groups who are commonly marginalized or excluded.

In a series of four blog posts I therefore aim to shortly introduce and discuss a number of currently popular concepts or approaches that are commonly employed to further the human rights of excluded or marginalized individuals or groups. I do this in order to provide some food for thought as to whether and to what extent associating the human rights framework with some or all of these ideas is suitable for making human rights a reality for everyone, particularly for those individuals or groups who seem to face particular challenges in the realization of their human rights such as, for instance, migrants, disabled persons or minorities. I aim to point out a number of pitfalls as well as the likely relationships and differences between the various ideas. This has the goal of questioning some of the underlying assumptions that are often taken as a given in international human rights law.

The four ideas I will discuss are diverse in their scope, approach and underlying paradigm. Some have been central to human rights for decades while others only recently emerged. Yet, they all seem to share an aspiration for the inclusion of all human beings into the human rights debate. In this blog posts series I aim to pinpoint a few points of concern in that respect.

In this first blog post I focus on the oldest and most well-established concept: human dignity. Subsequent posts will deal with the capabilities approach, intersectionality and, lastly, the notion of vulnerability. The last blog post will pay particular attention to the question of what the, arguably, most recent and currently fashionable notion of vulnerability can or cannot add to the other three ideas.

Since this blog post does not allow for an extensive discussion of human dignity but merely aims to raise a few questions, the concept of human dignity itself is not discussed in-depth. Interested readers can, for instance, refer to the edited volumes by McCrudden (ed., OUP 2013) and Düwell et al (eds., CUP 2014) for more detailed legal and theoretical discussions of the content and role of the concept.

What is human dignity? Human dignity is mentioned in many human rights documents and is often viewed as the main foundation of human rights. Most prominently, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights starts with a reference to “the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family”. What seems central to the arguments by proponents of human dignity as the main foundation of human rights is their interpretation of human dignity as emphasizing the empowerment of human beings. This understanding essentially reveals human dignity as a liberal concept that should facilitate an individual’s strive for autonomy and freedom.

Operating under this assumption and referring to human dignity as central guiding principle of human rights can provide a strong moral foundation for human rights and can foster the creation of internal coherence of international human rights law. Yet, growing disenchantment with how little the codification of international human rights law in international treaties has achieved especially for those individuals and groups that are (forced to live) at the margins of mainstream society has led to increasing criticism about the very assumption of an inherent human dignity. In the following I pinpoint three criticisms in this respect that raise questions with regard to the value of the concept as an effective argument for the realization of the human rights of these marginalized individuals or groups.

Firstly, the concept of human dignity has been criticized as overemphasizing “symbolic values” above actual human conditions.1 An emphasis on human dignity is thus considered to be “one-sided” and to not sufficiently take into account “our basic needs and our vulnerability” to which a suitable response would be “compassion without condescension”.2 Human dignity’s focus on individual autonomy and freedom makes it difficult to argue for such compassion or to even acknowledge basic needs and, particularly, inherent vulnerabilities of human beings.

Secondly, the historical record reveals how quickly states, societies or institutions might deny the human dignity of those individuals or groups that do not fit easily within mainstream society. There is no safeguard against redefining who is entitled to inherent human dignity. As Douzinas points out, atrocities such as slavery or the Holocaust painfully reveal that considering other humans as endowed with human dignity is no safe haven and can always be reversed:3

“There is no guarantee that affection will win over fear. Experience tells us however that when the fear of the other, the foreigner, the Jew, the refugee, becomes their institutional logic, human rights lose their protective value against the state”.4

Providing protection or assistance to other human beings on the basis of human dignity can thus easily lose its meaning.

Thirdly, the idea of the existence of an inherent human dignity does not clarify why human rights are justified but rather aggravates the problems secular societies have in finding a justification for human rights: the concept of human dignity is strongly linked to natural law ideas which rely on a higher order and ultimately religious morality.5 Alternatively, the concept of human dignity could be linked to Kant’s philosophy on dignity rather than to religion (although it can obviously be argued to what extent Kant was nevertheless influenced by and relied on Christianity). Yet, the concept would remain problematic: it would then lose its universal character as Kant grounds dignity in the human ability to reason and to be autonomous.6 Especially with regard to groups or individuals whose human rights are still far from being realized, human dignity does thus have little to offer. In the contexts of disability or displacement, for instance, the focus on autonomy neglects structural barriers to empowerment that cannot be overcome individually.

Overall, viewing human rights as founded on an inherent dignity of the human person should thus be reconsidered carefully especially in light of the, hitherto, limited realization of the human rights of those individuals or groups who do not fit this mainstream idea of an autonomous and self-sufficient individual human being. The concept of human dignity is therefore likely to hinder a more progressive and inclusive development of human rights. The next blog posts will pinpoint how three other approaches that can be employed to justify or engage with the international human rights law framework have tried to develop a more inclusive foundation (or at least a pragmatic justification and/or implementation mechanism) for human rights.
This blog post benefitted from discussions with colleagues at the University of Groningen and I would like to particularly thank Marie-Elske Gispen for sharing her views and work on human dignity with me.

1 Govert den Hartogh, ‘Is human dignity the ground of human rights?’ in Marcus Düwell, Jens Braarvig, Roger Brownsword and Dietmar Mieth (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Human Dignity: Interdisciplinary Perspectives (CUP 2014), 205-206.
2 Ibid., 205-206.
3 Costas Douzinas, The End of Human Rights (Hart Publishing, 2000), 372.
4 Ibid., 376.
5 Doris Schroeder, ‘Human Rights and Human Dignity: An Appeal to Separate the Conjoined Twins’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15:3 (2006), 323.
6 Ibid., 323, 329-330.

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Home › Blog › Related posts

A new take on human rights history? Investigating the United Nations’ Observances

13 June 2017 by Paul van Trigt
Rethinking Disability

In a recent debate about human rights historiography Lynn Hunt points to the presumption of leading scholars in the field that ‘the history of human rights must be first and foremost a political history in the most old-fashioned sense, that is, a history of diplomacy (covenants) and warfare (interventions).’ Therefore she emphasizes the relevance of the writing of ‘a social history of internationalism that is attentive to the role of women and non-Westerners’.

Read on ›

Theoretical Approaches to the Human Rights of Marginalized and Excluded Individuals or Groups – Part II: A Short Critique of the Capabilities Approach

25 September 2017 by Veronika Flegar
Rethinking Disability

This blog post is the second in a series of four in which I aim to disentangle some of the underlying assumptions of contemporary concepts and approaches that can be employed for justifying or engaging with the international human rights law framework.

Read on ›

Theoretical Approaches to the Human Rights of Marginalized and Excluded Individuals or Groups – Part III: A Short Critique of Intersectionality

2 October 2017 by Veronika Flegar
Rethinking Disability

This is the third blog post in a series of four in which I aim to highlight some of the underlying assumptions of concepts and approaches which are commonly employed to further the human rights of excluded or marginalized individuals or groups.

Read on ›

Theoretical Approaches to the Human Rights of Marginalized and Excluded Individuals or Groups – Part IV: A Short Critique of Vulnerability

16 October 2017 by Veronika Flegar
Rethinking Disability

This is the final blog post in a series of four. In this series I seek to highlight some of the underlying assumptions of four concepts or approaches that are commonly employed to further the human rights of excluded or marginalized individuals or groups.

Read on ›

Post navigation

Third International Disability Studies Conference Amsterdam, 30 November – 2 December 2017
Guest lecture by Anaïs Van Ertvelde: Good cripple, bad cripple. An introduction into critical disability studies

Team Rethinking Disability
Leiden University
Faculty of Humanities
Institute for History

Contact
rethinkingdisability@hum.leidenuniv.nl

@ERC_Rethinking Rethinking Disability
logo EU logo ERC
  • Cookies and Privacy
  • Website door Toeps
We use cookies on our website to give you the most relevant experience by remembering your preferences.
Cookie SettingsAccept All
Manage consent

Privacy Overview

This website uses cookies to improve your experience while you navigate through the website. Out of these, the cookies that are categorized as necessary are stored on your browser as they are essential for the working of basic functionalities of the website. We also use third-party cookies that help us analyze and understand how you use this website. These cookies will be stored in your browser only with your consent. You also have the option to opt-out of these cookies. But opting out of some of these cookies may affect your browsing experience.
Necessary
Always Enabled
Necessary cookies are absolutely essential for the website to function properly. These cookies ensure basic functionalities and security features of the website, anonymously.
CookieDurationDescription
cookielawinfo-checkbox-analytics11 monthsThis cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookie is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Analytics".
cookielawinfo-checkbox-functional11 monthsThe cookie is set by GDPR cookie consent to record the user consent for the cookies in the category "Functional".
cookielawinfo-checkbox-necessary11 monthsThis cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookies is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Necessary".
cookielawinfo-checkbox-others11 monthsThis cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookie is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Other.
cookielawinfo-checkbox-performance11 monthsThis cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookie is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Performance".
viewed_cookie_policy11 monthsThe cookie is set by the GDPR Cookie Consent plugin and is used to store whether or not user has consented to the use of cookies. It does not store any personal data.
Functional
Functional cookies help to perform certain functionalities like sharing the content of the website on social media platforms, collect feedbacks, and other third-party features.
Performance
Performance cookies are used to understand and analyze the key performance indexes of the website which helps in delivering a better user experience for the visitors.
Analytics
Analytical cookies are used to understand how visitors interact with the website. These cookies help provide information on metrics the number of visitors, bounce rate, traffic source, etc.
Advertisement
Advertisement cookies are used to provide visitors with relevant ads and marketing campaigns. These cookies track visitors across websites and collect information to provide customized ads.
Others
Other uncategorized cookies are those that are being analyzed and have not been classified into a category as yet.
SAVE & ACCEPT